What we mean when we say that we “construct” knowledge is
problematic, because we are often using language we inherit from the Piagetian
developmental tradition without fidelity to or understanding of that tradition.
According to Piaget, learning results when acting on
objects, which disturbs our cognitive “equilibrium” and in turn forces us to
either assimilate the new experience that confirms or extends our existing
cognitive structures or accommodate the new learning that corrects the new contradictions
to our cognitive structures. These
things appear to happen “naturally,” tacitly.
Few academics who declare that we “construct knowledge” show any
appreciation of the roots of their language.
It is not always clear in Piaget what kind of “structure” he
is referring to, though, “behind the scenes” cognitive structures or conscious
mental models derived from reflection on our experience. Nevertheless, Piaget and his constructivist
successors, heirs to Kantian idealism, are adamant about our inability to know
the world directly, that we “filter” the world through conceptual schemes. So far so good.
The rub: Piagetian
understanding of learning is so colored by his studies of pre-school age children
that his theories are applied universally, where they appear to break
down. His justification seems to be
analogical: If process A describes
learning by an infant and, as biological creatures, we have evolved by learning
the same way, then juvenile and adult learning reflects or even requires the
same process. Therefore it, too, must
involve active engagement with an object.
And so college teachers are increasingly transforming their classrooms
into hives of small group inquiry.
Not bad in itself, the “active” model has to be stretched to
accommodate lecture and reading, probably the oldest university teaching
methods we practice. Much of our reading
is for information that we do not have the experience or capability or time to
discover for ourselves. Particle
physics, brain physiology, or even Piaget’s developmental psychology come to
mind. I suspect there are others. Piaget’s theory does not consider these
constraints when applied to the classroom.
Lectures are sometimes self-conscious interpretations of course material
(Worthen), sometimes simply replacements for the reading students are unable or
unwilling to do. Unlike many other
teaching methods, lecture has one important advantage over others: experts in their field—teachers—are able to
tie loose ends together in the context of their classroom to achieve some
coherence in the material students are inquiring about.
I have already argued elsewhere that all learning is active,
so I won’t spend time defending these practices again. Instead, I’d like to explore Piaget’s
understanding of knowledge versus the contemporary philosophical position that
knowledge is justified belief.
If we can have no access to the world except through our
conceptions of it, and if our conceptions of it are colored by our personal
“interests” and values, then justification for a constructivist can involve
only the absence of contradiction, pragmatic viability” (does it work for the
individual?), and social confirmation (Cardellini). If justification is thus limited, then we
will have trouble explaining the persistent ability of quantum mechanics,
despite what Einstein or anyone else felt about it, to provide the
justification required for its assertions to be true, because it is successful at “making predictions so accurate
as to defy belief” (Derman 5).
Similarly, in the literature classroom the various schools
of literary criticism have to start with the reality of the text (Rabinowitz 30). We don’t (or shouldn’t) honor an
interpretation of War and Peace as
prototypical science fiction. Here,
Hirsch’s distinction between meaning and significance is useful (8). If we are going to talk about the same novel,
we have to agree who the characters are and what events take place, using
evidence from the text and backgrounded literary conventions. When we disagree about these, someone is
generally guilty of misreading, and we can settle these differences by
referring to the text. How we assign
significance to those characters and events is what divides us and leads to
arguments, interesting and petty alike, that references to the text generally
can’t resolve.
Just as the text constrains our interpretations and the laws
of physics hold whether we know them or not, external reality limits the scope
of our understanding and efficacy (Weisman).
We understand this world through the models or schemas we build of
it. Piaget explains in structuralist
terms how we interact with that external reality, but even in his telling, it
is the external, physical fact that imposes itself on our schema, not the other
way around. Despite the infant’s
apparent belief that the toy, hidden under the blanket, no longer exists, it in
fact does. Our knowledge is justified,
not by our schema, our models, but instead by the realities our schemas
encounter.
This is a blessing.
If we are dependent on our subjective filtering of the world, and our
only justification comes from whether it works (Cardellini), we leave ourselves
hopelessly vulnerable to self-deception.
Our resistance to external information that contradicts our schemas is a
well-known subject in studies of cognitive dissonance, the Dunning Kruger
effect, and biased assimilation. There
are good reasons for some of that resistance—physicists did not allow the
announcement from Cern that neutrinos were found to travel faster than light to
disrupt their Einsteinian view of the universe (Brufiel). The wisdom of their resistance was confirmed
a year later (Cho). Still, disconfirmation
is all too often resisted in ways dysfunctional and destructive of self and
community. Mental illness, addiction,
violence, learning disabilities, and political extremism (cf Hoffer, The True Believer) might be rooted in
distinguishable constructions that may intensify evil effects. This is not something constructivism can
explain, because what “works” is left to individuals to decide.
Social constraints are growing more feeble as well, and so
offer fewer sources of “perturbation.” True believers can isolate themselves
from contradiction by engaging only with those who think as they do, through
social media and ideological enclaves.
Bill Bishop, in The Big Sort,
documents how, over the last thirty-five years or so, Americans have chosen to
move to places where the people are just like them in terms of race, education,
religion, economics, and politics. We
often nurture gated minds.
This resistance to disconfirmation is real. A constructivist psychology offers no hope
for the deluded if valuation is strictly personal and correction is dependent
on weakened social influences. What kind
of perturbation can there be in such a self-protected psyche? Disillusion comes soon after “reality sets
in.” Soviet sympathizers in the West of
the twenties and thirties eventually came to realize the brutality of
Stalinism. It required an
awakening.
Similarly, regardless of our awareness, our knowledge, our
interpretations, our conceptions, our concern, lurk other realities. Poverty is real. Climate change is real. War is real and so, too, the dislocations it
causes. ISIL’s beheading of non-Muslims
and even Muslims is real. Attacks on
Muslim girls in school are real. They
need not be “constructed.”
There is a great deal in the universe that exists that we
have not discovered. That word “discovered”
is operative in a realistic approach to learning. We discover not only by confronting data and
inductively generalizing from it, but also by hearing and reading the conclusions
of others who do go through that process.
Others’ insights, spoken or written directly and explicitly, are often
new to us, and help us make sense of the world and ourselves. Sometimes, we adapt or accept wholesale other
people’s constructions—their integrations and models and, occasionally,
ideologies. Some people call that
entering a tradition or a profession or a practice.
However, it is claimed that such behavior is not indicative
of individual agency and power.
Consequently, someone like Andrea Lunsford, a ubiquitous writer on
issues regarding college composition, can put on the cover of her textbook The Everyday Writer, “Today’s students
want to be producers of knowledge, not just consumers of things others have
said.” Yet she has written a book full of direct, explicit
instruction—something an “other” has said.
We are all “consumers of things others have said,” because that is one
way we learn. Only in the contemporary academy
is that equated with crass commercialism.
Through that rhetoric we aim at an admirable end: increasing the empowerment and agency of our
students. But traditional methods of
teaching and learning exist because they, too, work, and have for
centuries. Otherwise, how could it be
that teachers have been wrong for so long, while universities the world over
have produced so many educated, knowledgeable, inventive people? If the construction of knowledge is not a
wholly adequate description of what we are doing when we learn, why use the
term?
My answer is that the language of constructivism has become
the shibboleth of the academy, a sign of membership, because we are au courant with contemporary thought and
practice. Hardly a researcher or writer
on education can avoid defining learning as construction.
As a consequence, we find ways to widen the circle of
permissible pedagogy so as to leave our current practices intact (Carillo 5; Worthen). And, contrary to constructivist ideology, we
require students to provide verifiable evidence for their arguments. We are still wedded to fact-based
justification in which we look to the real world for confirmation (Lunsford
136). Our rhetoric is a nod and a wink
to the likes of Piaget and von Glasersfeld, but our intuition and experience
generally prevail. It’s time to stop
being defensive.
References
Bishop,
Bill. The Big Sort: Why
the Clustering of Like-Minded America is Tearing Us Apart.
New York: Houghton Mifflin, 2008.
Brufiel,
Jeff. “Particles Found to Travel Faster
Than Speed of Light.” Nature. 22 September
2011. Web. 19 Feb 2016 http://www.scientificamerican.com/article/particles-found-to-travel/
Cardellini,
Liberato. “The Foundations of Radical
Constructivism: An Interview with Ernst
von Glasersfeld.” Foundations of
Chemistry. 8: 177-187. 2006. Print.
Carillo, Ellen
C. Securing
a Place for Reading in Composition: The
Importance of Teaching for Transfer.
Logan, UT: Utah State UP, 2015.
Cho, Adrian. “Once
Again, Physicists Debunk Faster-Than-Light Neutrinos.” Science
AAAS. 8 Jun 2012. 19 Feb 2016. Web.
Derman, Emanuel. Models. Behaving. Badly.: Why Confusing Illusion with Reality Can Lead
to Disaster on Wall Street and in Life.
New York: Free Press, 2011.
Hirsch, E. D.,
Jr. Validity
in Interpretation. New Haven: Yale
UP, 1967.
Hoffer, Eric. The
True Believer: Thoughts on the Nature of
Mass Movements. New York: Harper & Row, 1951.
Lunsford,
Andrea. The Everyday Writer. 6th Edition. New York: Bedford St. Martins, 2016.
Rabinowitz, Peter
J. Before
Reading: Narrative Conventions and the
Politics of Interpretation. Ithaca,
NY: Cornell UP, 1987.
Weisman,
David. Truth’s Debt to Value. New
Haven: Yale UP, 1997.
Worthen,
Molly. “Lecture Me. Really.”
NY Times. 17 October
2015. SR1. Print.
No comments:
Post a Comment