One of the great puzzles to me is Piaget’s research on
object permanence. It is a mark of
intellectual advancement to him when an infant of around nine months is able to
realize (odd, isn’t it, how realism sneaks into the most innocent words!) that
when a toy is hidden underneath a blanket that it still exists, regardless of
the fact that the child cannot see it.
Yet Piaget denied that we form pictures of the real world (S
15). Through assimilation and
accommodation alone our cognitive structures are altered by our experience and
mistakes corrected. But how does such a
process account for the toddler (around nine months) suddenly grasping the
notion that the toy is under the blanket, when she has not had the prior
experience of its hidden existence? Our
language suggests a different paradigm:
we use the word insight to
explain a mental visualization of something that may or may not exist. We “see” the problem or its solution, envisioning what is not before us or
what a course of action might lead to. We
then act on our insight, and dis-cover what we have hypothesized, however
incoherently, is there. In the process,
our child finds her toy, which was, as she then realizes, there all along.
It’s an interesting word, “discover.” Piaget writes, “from an empiricist point of
view, a ‘discovery’ is new for the person who makes it, but what is discovered
was already in existence in external reality and there is therefore no
construction of new realities” (GE 77). He
disputes this. Yet it is precisely this
sense in which Piaget uses the word “discover” or “discovery” several times in Structuralism (5, 24, 27, 32, 45, 56, 61).
Piaget can write, “structure was discovered” (S 55),
implying that structure existed before we discovered it. The toy existed under the blanket before the
child uncovered it. The Pythagorean
Theorem existed before Pythagoras—or whoever—discovered it. (This is not
Platonism: it is the nature of a right
triangle that the sum of the squares of the sides should equal the square of
the hypotenuse.)
If we have discovered a theorem and toys and structures, it is
likely we have discovered much else that was “external,” indifferent to our
knowledge of it. Once discovered, we
can share our new knowledge by objectifying it through language (Popper 25). That is how the Pythagorean Theorem means the
same thing everywhere.
We do not need to dispute that we understand the world
through conceptual frameworks that we construct, but those are amenable to
change in a way that object permanence is not.
Though Thomas Kuhn’s Structure of
Scientific Revolutions has served as justification for Constructivism, Boghossian
points out that Kuhn documents the empirical data that led to scientific
revolutions. They are facts that are external,
that defy explanation by the prevailing paradigm. At a certain point, accommodation is not
possible according to Kuhn’s account:
only a new paradigm will serve.
References
Boghossian, Paul.
Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism. Oxford:
Clarendon, 2006. Print.
Kuhn, Thomas
S. The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Second
Edition. Chicago: University of Chicago, 1970. Print
Piaget, Jean. Genetic
Epistemology (GE). Trans. Eleanor Duckworth. New York: Columbia UP, 1970. Print.
Woodbridge Lectures Delivered at Columbia University in October 1968. Print.
Piaget, Jean. Structuralism (S).
Trans. Chaninah Maschler. New York: Basic, 1970. Print.
Popper, Karl R.
"Conjectural Knowledge: My Solution to the Problem of Induction." Objective
Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Clarendon. 1-31. Print.
No comments:
Post a Comment