The strongest argument against any theory is that it fails
to explain the behavior it describes, or that its predictions are demonstrated
to be mistaken. This is the procedure of
falsification that the philosopher Karl Popper is widely known for.
So let’s take another look at various Piagetian claims that
have been refuted or more simply explained in empirical studies, many of which
were designed to eliminate flaws in Piaget’s original work.
A brief digression, though, is in order. Contemporary constructivists will often
dispute empirical projects, claiming that they are founded on the mistaken
belief that the data purport to describe the “real” world, when in fact they
are products of a theory that inherently cannot describe the so-called real
world (vG “Exposition” 3). This despite
the fact that Piaget himself considered his own research “empirical”: his entire project is based on interpreting
experiences of children performing specific acts in the course of solving some
kind of problem. He insisted he was
doing science, after all. Piaget’s
associates and defenders acknowledge that the master’s claims were hypotheses,
some of which he expected to be upheld, others not.
I will be referring to papers contained in books edited by
Sohan and Celia Modgil on the one hand and Linda Siegel and Charles Brainerd on
the other.
Learning for Piaget is explained “genetically” by observing
signs of cognitive development in infants and children. He has detected—discovered?—that the
behaviors are part of cognitive systems or structures that develop by
age-dependent stages and permit the child to solve physical problems such as
the disappearance of a toy (does it still exist?) or the conservation of liquid
(does the amount change when poured into a differently shaped container?). Knowledge that depends on the attainment of
one stage cannot be learned until the previous stage has been attained and
fully assimilated.
Several experimenters have challenged Piaget’s assertions
about stages, however, and they have found that Piaget’s verbal interaction
with his subjects confounded his results (Siegel), that training, which Piaget
claims is unnecessary and generally unworkable (Brainerd 82), in fact succeeds
in significantly advancing children’s cognitive abilities (Brainerd), and that
a child’s ability to perform in a Piagetian experiment depends often on local
factors. For specific documentation on
the latter, I quote a longish paragraph from Joan Tamburrini of the Froebel
Institute:
Over the past decade or so (the
article was published in 1982), a number of studies have yielded results
suggesting that a subject’s performance on a Piagetian-type of task is much
more likely than we have hitherto supposed to depend on various situational
factors. At the sensorimotor stage of
development differences have been found with respect to the concept of object
permanence. For example, Bower (1974),
Kessen, Haith and Salatapek (1970), and Cornell (1978) have found that infants
as young or younger than those who do not search for an object that has
disappeared from view in the standard Piagetian tests do so in other specific
situations. In relation to concrete
operational thinking various studies have purported to show that young
children’s capabilities are greater than the results of standard Piagetian
tests would lead one to suppose. Studies
by Borke (1971, 1973, 1975) and Hughes (1978) have reputedly shown that
children much younger than seven or eight years of age are able to think
non-egocentrically. Bryant and Trabasso
(1971) have claimed that under certain conditions children can solve transitive
inference problems at an age when they would fail on the orthodox Piagetian
test. Donaldson (1978) has reported a
study showing that in a modification of one of Piaget’s tests children conserved
numerical quantity at a younger age than is usual in the standard version of
the test. By contrast, Watson and
Johnson-Laird (1972) have reported studies which show that adult subjects of
well above average intelligence who, it is therefore presumed, would succeed on
one of Piaget’s tests for formal operational thought failed to solve problems
which, though they differ in content from the standard Piagetian tests,
required the same structures of through that Piaget calls “formal operations
(312).
The philosopher Owen Flanagan acknowledges the weaknesses of
Piaget’s theory of stages, but suggests that his basic structuralism can
survive without it (148-149). However,
similar objections have challenged Piaget’s insistence that logical structures precede
language (Moore and Harris find parallel development), that Piaget’s
development process is universal (Buck-Morss), that Piaget’s understanding of
children’s propositional logic is accurate (Ennis), that advanced structures
can develop from more basic structures (Flanagan), that equilibration, Piaget’s
primary mechanism for judging cognitive “adequacy,” is at root inadequate
(Phillips).
In our own experience we know that students learn from
reading texts that are full of conclusions and persuasive interpretations. Similarly, they learn from lectures,
especially those well thought through and delivered. These methods, centuries old, constructivists would
consider a hijacking of the true learning process, in which students discover
through their own inquiry, thereby “constructing” their own knowledge. But we know, because we read books of history, literary criticism, sociology, biology,
physics, and even Piagetian psychology, that conclusions by others are
instructive for us as well as our students.
Learning does not need to begin by inventing the wheel. In fact, constructivists do not do this
either. They read (and write) books like
the rest of us. They have listened to
and even given lectures. If they learn
from books and their audiences learn from their lectures, then perhaps these
illegitimate pedagogies aren’t so outdated or illegitimate after all.
I have to wonder, then, how constructivists can recover the
explanatory power of a theory whose universe is so circumscribed.
References:
Brainerd, Charles
J. “Learning Research and Piagetian Theory.” Alternatives to Piaget. Ed.
Linda S. Siegel and Charles J. Brainerd.
New York: Academic, 1978. Print.
69-110.
Buck-Morss,
Susan. “Socio-economic Bias in Piaget’s
Theory and its Implication for Cross Cultural Studies.” Jean Piaget: Consensus and Controversy. Ed. Sohan Modgil and Celia Modgil. New York:
Praegar, 1982. Print. 261-272.
Ennis, Robert
H. “Children's Ability to Handle Piaget's Propositional Logic: A Conceptual Critique.” Jean Piaget: Consensus and
Controversy. Ed. Sohan Modgil and
Celia Modgil. New York: Praegar, 1982. Print. 101-130.
Flanagan,
Owen. The Science of the Mind.
Second Edition. Cambridge:
Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 1984.
Print.
Moore, Timothy E.
and Adrienne E. Harris. “Language and
Thought in Piagetian Theory.” Alternatives
to Piaget. Ed. Linda S. Siegel and
Charles J. Brainerd. New York: Academic, 1978. Print. 169-200.
Phillips,
Denis. “Perspectives on Piaget as
Philosopher: The Tough, Tender-minded
Syndrome.” Jean Piaget: Consensus and
Controversy. Ed. Sohan Modgil and
Celia Modgil. New York: Praegar, 1982. 13-30.
Popper, Karl R.
"Conjectural Knowledge: My Solution to the Problem of Induction." Objective
Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Clarendon. 1-31. Print.
Siegel, Linda S. “The
Relationship of Language and Thought in the Preoperational Child: A
Reconsideration of Nonverbal Alternatives to Piagetian Tasks.” Alternatives to Piaget. Ed. Linda S. Siegel and Charles J.
Brainerd. New York: Academic, 1978. Print. 43-68.
Tamburrini, Joan.
“Some Educational Implications of Piaget’s Theory.” Jean Piaget: Consensus and Controversy. Ed. Sohan Modgil and Celia Modgil. New York:
Praegar, 1982. Print. 309-325.
No comments:
Post a Comment